I have become more convinced recently that capitalism is implicitly pervasive
in our conceptions and affects our actions including teaching. Without
understanding capitalism critically, no innovation or radical change is
possible for our stagnating practice, my field, English Language Teaching,
included. A Japanese translation of Moishe's Postone (1993)Time, Labor, and
Social Domination (Cambridge University Press) has recently been
published and well-received in Japan, and I also find this book fascinating. (I
read the translation first and only important parts in the original English
book).
The book is based on the author's dissertation for Fachbereich Gesellschaftswissenschaften at the J. W. Goethe-Universität in Frankfurt, and the writing style is dialectic. This style may discourage some Anglo-American readers who prefer what they regard as the 'straight line of argument', but there are some things in this world that may better be elucidated by dialectics. Following is my note of the book.
This book is, as its subtitle says, a reinterpretation of Marx's critical theory, and departs from the traditional Marxism. The traditional Marxism is defined as follows:
The book is based on the author's dissertation for Fachbereich Gesellschaftswissenschaften at the J. W. Goethe-Universität in Frankfurt, and the writing style is dialectic. This style may discourage some Anglo-American readers who prefer what they regard as the 'straight line of argument', but there are some things in this world that may better be elucidated by dialectics. Following is my note of the book.
This book is, as its subtitle says, a reinterpretation of Marx's critical theory, and departs from the traditional Marxism. The traditional Marxism is defined as follows:
all theoretical approaches that analyze capitalism from the standpoint of labor and characterize that society essentially in terms of class relations, structured by private ownership of the means of production and a market-regulated economy. Relations of domination are understood primarily in terms of class domination and exploitation. (p. 7)
While the traditional Marxism is a critique of capitalism from the standpoint of labor, this reinterpretation is a critique of labor in capitalism (p. 5). Capitalism, in turn, is conceptualized "in terms of a historically specific form of social interdependence with an impersonal and seemingly objective character" (p. 3). Analysis of this seemingly objective social interdependence constitutes a critical assessment of "the form of modern society itself" (p. 66).
One of the important features of modern society that is critically assessed is social domination that capitalism imposes upon us.
In Marx's analysis, social domination in capitalism does not, on its
most fundamental level, consist in the domination of people by other people,
but in the domination of people by abstract social structures that people
themselves constitute. Marx sought to grasp this form of abstract, structural
domination --which encompasses, and extends beyond, class domination-- with his
categories of the commodity and capital. (p. 30)
People are dominated by capitalism they made and maintain, which is driven by capital that promotes production of commodities. In other words, people are alienated (p. 30) because the Subject of their history in their society is not them, but capital. I'll explain how specifically capital becomes the Subject of modern society below.
Our analysis of capitalism should start from the fundamental level, value, as it affects the more specific levels.
this approach implicitly treats as socially constituted the level of
structured preknowledge that Kant interprets as a transcendental a
priori condition of knowledge. ... It grasps this preknowledge as
a preconscious structure of consciousness which is socially formed, and neither
posits it as a universal, transcendental a priori nor bases it
on an assumed absolute knowledge. ... This interpretation suggests that
epistemology becomes, in Marx's theory, radical
as social epistemology. (pp. 218-219)
According to Marx, value in capitalistic society, commodity value (Warenwerte), a more exact term I prefer (See p. 52 ofDas Kapitel I) , has two factors: use value and exchange value (Please refer to articles: Marx's dialectics according to David Harvey http://yosukeyanase.blogspot.jp/2012/08/marxs-dialectics-according-to-david.html, and (if you can read Japanese) On the commodity according to Marx http://yanaseyosuke.blogspot.jp/2012/08/blog-post_14.html) . For reasons I don't understand, Postone doesn't use the term of exchange value very often, and often contrasts use value and value. But his point is clear: the contrast between the value that is qualitatively different for each individual (use value) and (commodity) value that is standardized socially and quantitative for measurement.
Capitalistic society is unique in that it prioritizes (commodity) value over use value, for in order to produce something as a commodity for living (either as goods or service), people need to produce it for exchange in a far more amount than they need for themselves. Value of a commodity in capitalistic society is seen mostly as exchange value for people in general in society rather than as use value for its producer. Value as commodity value is more social and abstract than individual and specific.
As Marx says, "The wealth of societies in which the capitalist mode of production prevails appears as an 'immense collection of commodities'; the individual commodity appears as its elementary form. (Penguin translation of Das Kapitel, p.125), and we begin to disregard the material side of use value and prize the social side of (commodity) value. Wealth in capitalistic societies is less about material wealth than socially constituted value.
This different conception of wealth makes different types of
society. Where wealth is regarded as material wealth, people are engaged in concrete
labor produce mostly for use value with the help of Nature.
The difference between material wealth and value is central to the
Marxian critique of capitalism. It is rooted, according to Marx, in the double
character of labor in that social formation. Material wealth is created by
concrete labor, but labor is not the sole source of material wealth; rather,
this form of wealth results from the transformation of matter by people with
the aid of natural forces. Material wealth, then, arises from the interactions
of humans and nature, as mediated by useful labor. (p. 194)
On the other hand, in capitalistic societies where wealth results from socially constituted relations, people produce commodities for exchange value and are engaged more in abstract labor.
Here, we should clarify the double characters of use
value/(commodity) value and of concrete labor/abstract (human)
labor. This is how Postone summarizes.
Marx begins Capital with an analysis of the
commodity as a good, a use value, that at the same time, is a [commodity]
value. He then relates these two dimensions of the commodity to the double
character of the labor it incorporates. As a particular use value, the
commodity is the product of a particular concrete labor; as a
[commodity] value, it is the objectification of abstract human labor.
(p. 127 square brackets and emphasis added).
Abstract human labor, or abstract labor, is measured by "socially necessary labor time."
Socially necessary labour-time is the
labour-time required to produce any use-value under the conditions of
production normal for a given society and with the average degree of skill and
intensity of labour prevalent in that society. (Penguin translation of p. 53 of Das
Kapitel I)
So in capitalistic societies where people produce commodities for exchange whose value as wealth is measured by the unit of the socially necessary labor time, people's work is estimated more as abstract labor than as concrete labor. In capitalism, concrete labor that is directly for material wealth matters less , and people must be engaged in abstract labor even when they may already have plenty of material wealth for themselves, for they have no means of living other than earning money for purchasing commodities they need by producing commodities they can produce whether it is goods or service. They earn money in proportion to the 'value' of capitalism that is determined by the socially necessary time as abstract labor.
So in capitalistic societies where people produce commodities for exchange whose value as wealth is measured by the unit of the socially necessary labor time, people's work is estimated more as abstract labor than as concrete labor. In capitalism, concrete labor that is directly for material wealth matters less , and people must be engaged in abstract labor even when they may already have plenty of material wealth for themselves, for they have no means of living other than earning money for purchasing commodities they need by producing commodities they can produce whether it is goods or service. They earn money in proportion to the 'value' of capitalism that is determined by the socially necessary time as abstract labor.
The determinations of value, the dominant form of wealth in
capitalism, are very different from those of material wealth. Value is peculiar
in that, though a form of wealth, it does not express directly the relation of
humans to nature but the relations among people as mediated by labor. Hence,
according to Marx, nature does not enter directly into value's constitution at
all. As a social mediation, value is constituted by (abstract) labor alone: it
is an objectification of the historically specific social dimension of labor in
capitalism as a socially mediating activity, as the "substance" of
alienated relations. Its magnitude is, then, not a direct expression of the
quantity of products created or of the power of natural forces harnessed; it
is, rather, a function only of abstract labor time. In other words, although
increased productivity does result in more material wealth, it does not result
in more value per unit of time. As a form of wealth that is also a form of
social relations, value does not express directly the acquired productive
abilities of humanity. (p. 195)
But it is not true that capitalistic societies estimate only abstract labor, abstract time and (commodity) value. Abstract labor/concrete labor, abstract time/concrete time and use value as wealth/(commodity) value are in dialectical dynamic.
I have focused thus far on the centrality to Marx's critical theory
of his conception of the dual character of the fundamental social forms of
capitalist society, and have tried to clarify the nature of, and distinction
between, the value dimension of the forms (abstract labor, value, abstract
time) and the use value dimension (concrete labor, material wealth,
concrete time). At this point, I can examine their interrelations. The
nonidentity of these two dimensions is not simply a static opposition; rather,
the two moments of labor in capitalism, as productive activity and as a
socially mediating activity, are mutually determining in a way that gives rise
to an immanent dialectical dynamic. (p. 287)
Commodities are the medium of this dialectical dynamic. This is why Marx put the chapter on the commodity at the beginning of Capital as the most important part.
From a transhistorical starting point, Marx moves to a historically
determinate one. The category "commodity," in Marx's analysis, does
not simply refer to an object, but to a historically specific,
"objective" form of social relations -- a structuring and structured
form of social practice that constitutes a radically new form of social
interdependence. This form is characterized by a historically specific duality
purportedly at the core of the social system: use value and value, concrete
labor and abstract labor. (p. 139)
It is absolutely critical that unlike other forms of societies, capitalistic societies makes social relations "objective" or "object-like" by commodities, money, and capital. Being objective or object-like, our relations become abstract, formal, homogeneous, standardized, and only quantitative.
Each commodity has not only its specific concrete qualities,
measured in concrete material quantities, but all commodities share in common
value, a nonmanifest abstract quality with (as we shall see) a temporally
determined magnitude. The magnitude of their value is a function of abstract
measure rather than of concrete material quantity. As a social form, the
commodity is completely independent of its material content. This form is not,
in other words, the form of qualitatively specific objects but is abstract and
can be grasped mathematically. It possesses "formal" characteristics.
Commodities are both particular, sensual objects (and are valued as such by the
buyer) and values, moments of an abstractly homogeneous substance that is
mathematically divisible and measurable (for example, in terms of time and
money). (p. 175)
Measured mathematically, labor and time of people are turned into commodities, and ultimately into money as the medium for universal exchange. Postone summarizes Marx.
He [= Marx] argues that in a society where the commodity is then
universal form of the product, money does not render commodities commensurable;
rather, it is an expression, a necessary form of appearance, of their
commensurability, of the fact that labor function as a socially mediating
activity. (p. 264)
A capitalistic society is mediated human labor and time that takes the form of commodities that are universally exchanged with money, a quantitative unit of measurement.
Furthermore, money changes into capital in capitalism. A producer may only use money to purchase what he needs: Exchange of Commodity 1 (C1) --say, his labor power-- with money (M) and then another exchange of M with Commodity 2 (C2) --what he purchases. He may be happy in this exchange of C1-M-C2 as long as he is ready to give C1 for C2, which are qualitatively different and not exactly comparable in quantity. However, for a capitalist, exchange is M1-C-M2 (he first invests money (M1) to produce a commodity (C) and receives money (M2) in return. Here, the comparison between the start (M1) and the end (M2) are purely quantitative, for they are not qualitatively different at all. If M2 he receives for M1 is equal in amount, there is no point of investing. M2 must be more than M1, and added quantity is called surplus value. Using the formula of M-C-M' to mean what I wrote as M1-C-M2, Postone says.
The formula M-C-M' does not refer to a process whereby wealth in
general is increased but to a process whereby value is increased.
Marx calls the quantitative difference between M and M' surplus value.
Value becomes capital, according to Marx, as a result of a process of
valorization of value, whereby is magnitude is increased. ... The formula M-C-M'
is intended to represent an ongoing process: M' is not simply withdrawn at the
end of the process as money, but remains part of the circuit of capital. This
circuit, in other worlds, is actually M-C-M'-C-M"-C... (p. 268)
Capital, then, is a category of movement, of expansion; it is a
dynamic category, "value in motion." This social form is alienated,
quasi-independent, exerts a mode of abstract compulsion and constraint on
people, and is in motion. Consequently, Marx accords it the attribute of
agency. His initial determination of capital, then, is as self-valorizing
value, as the self-moving substance that is subject. He describes this self-moving
subjective-objective social form in terms of a continuous, ceaseless process of
value's self-expansion. ... Capital has no fixed, final form, but appears at
different stages of its spiraling path in the form of money and commodities.
Value, then, is unfolded by Marx as the core of a form of social mediation that
constitutes social objectivity and subjectivity, and is intrinsically dynamic:
it is a form of social mediation that necessarily exists in objectified,
materialized form, but is neither identical with, nor an inherent property of,
its materialized form, whether in the shape of money or goods. ...
The movement of capital is without limit, without end. As self-valorizing value, it appears as pure process. In dealing with the category of capital, then, one is dealing with a central category of a society that becomes characterized by a constant directional movement with no determinate external telos, a society driven by production for the sake of production, by a process that exists for the sake of process. This expansion, this ceaseless motion is, within the framework of Marx's analysis, intrinsically related to the temporal dimension of value. (p. 269)
The movement of capital is without limit, without end. As self-valorizing value, it appears as pure process. In dealing with the category of capital, then, one is dealing with a central category of a society that becomes characterized by a constant directional movement with no determinate external telos, a society driven by production for the sake of production, by a process that exists for the sake of process. This expansion, this ceaseless motion is, within the framework of Marx's analysis, intrinsically related to the temporal dimension of value. (p. 269)
Surplus value, assessed only quantitatively not qualitatively, is now both the end and the means of capitalistic societies. Surplus value drives capitalistic societies as the agent and subject.
Labor, understood as a useful interaction with nature to get what people need in non-capitalistic societies, is now abstract labor standardized according to the objective abstract time in capitalism. As we rely more on commodities for survival than on our own concrete, useful labor, we become standardized according to abstract labor and time to earn money, and involved in capitalism as a means of ever-increasing drive of capital. We are driven to produce commodities endlessly.
The goal of production in capitalism is neither the material goods
produced nor the reflexive effects of laboring activity on the producer, but
value, or more precisely, surplus value. Value, however, is a purely
quantitative goal; there is no qualitative difference between the value of
wheat and that of weapons. Value is the objectification of abstract labor -- of
labor as an objective means of acquiring goods it has not produced. Thus
production for (surplus) value is production where the goal itself is a means.
Hence, production in capitalism necessarily is quantitatively oriented, toward
ever-increasing amounts of surplus value. This is the basis of Marx's analysis
of production in capitalism as production for the sake of production. (p. 181)
We no longer own or control our labor and production. We don't labor or produce for ourselves but for capitalism. Our labor and production are now separated from our life. We're alienated by and from our own labor and production.
Marx's determinations of value and the process of its creation imply
that labor, which in the labor process is defined as purposeful action that
regulates and directs human interaction with nature, is separated from its
purpose in the process of creating value. The goal of the expenditure of labor
power no longer is bound intrinsically to the specific nature of that labor;
rather, this goal, despite appearances, is independent of
the qualitative character of the labor expended -- it is the
objectification of labor time itself. That is to say, the expenditure of labor
power is not a means to another end, but, as a means, has itself become an
"end." This goal is given by the alienated structures constituted by
(abstract) labor itself. As a goal, it is very singular; it is not only
extrinsic to the specificity of (concrete) labor but also is
posited independently of the social actors' will. (p. 281)
As laborers, we may labor long or short, but not valued by our specific work; We are only valued by the framework of capitalism: abstract labor and abstract labor. We are subsumed in capitalism.
When labor mediates and constitutes social relations, it becomes the
central element of a totality that dominates individuals -- who, nevertheless,
are free from relations of personal domination: " Labour, which is thus
measured by time, does not seem, indeed, to be the labour of different
subjects, but on the contrary the different working individuals seem to be mere
organs of the labour."
... Marx analyzes the subsumption of individuals under abstract objective structures as a feature of the social form grasped by the category of capital. (p. 192)
... Marx analyzes the subsumption of individuals under abstract objective structures as a feature of the social form grasped by the category of capital. (p. 192)
This is how Postone criticizes labor; "Labor itself constitutes a social mediation in leau of overt social relations" (p. 150); "In other words, labor grounds its own social character in capitalism by virtue of its historically specific function as a socially mediating activity. In that sense, Labor in capitalism becomes its own social ground (p. 151)
Commodities and money started as means for the life of people. But as they develop into the media that constitutes capitalistic societies and move for their own life, not necessarily for the life of people. We may no longer be using commodities and money; commodities and money may be using us. We may be objectively dominated by a capitalistic society we live and work in.
The social relations that fundamentally define capitalism are
"objective" in character and constitute a "system," because
they are constituted by labor as a historically specific socially mediating
activity, that is, by an abstract, homogeneous, and objectifying form of
practice. (p. 158)
Domination of people in capitalism is abstract and impersonal, unlike the domination by capitalists which the traditional Marxism assumed.
The initial determination of such abstract social compulsion is that
individuals are compelled to produce and exchange commodities in order to
survive. This compulsion exerted is not a function of direct social domination,
as is the case, for example, with slave or serf labor; it is, rather a function
of "abstract" and "objective" social structures, and
represents a form of abstract, impersonal domination. Ultimately,
this form of domination is not grounded in any person, class or institution;
its ultimate locus is the pervasive structuring social forms of capitalist
society that are constituted by determinate forms of social practice. (p. 159)
We are not only dominated but also propelled to work harder through the dialectic of capitalism. Because value is primarily determined by abstract labor time, not by concrete labor that produce material wealth, our value is diminished every time our productivity is increased through the introduction and spread of machines, for example. Because of the innovation, we may produce twice as much as we used to in terms of material wealth, but as we produce it half the amount of abstract time now, the material wealth produced after the innovation has only half the value, and we have to expend twice as much abstract labor time to earn the same value in the form of money. The innovation produces twice as much material wealth, but it also forces us to labor twice as much. We labor more, but we may not be all the happier. This is the treadmill effect of capitalism.
The peculiarity of the dynamic -- and this is crucial -- is its treadmill
effect. Increased productivity increases the amount of value produced
per unit of time -- until this productivity becomes generalized; at that point
the magnitude of value yielded in that time period, because of its abstract and
general temporal determination, falls back to its previous level. This results
in a new determination of the social labor hour and a new base level of
productivity. What emerges, then, is a dialectic of transformation
and reconstitution;: the socially general levels of productivity and the
quantitative determinations of socially necessary labor time change, yet these
changes reconstitute the point of departure, that is, the social
labor hour and the base level of productivity. (pp. 289-290)
Because of the treadmill effect of capitalism, our history may now be unidirectional: people are to work harder to sustain capitalism.
The dialectic of the two dimensions of labor in capitalism, then,
can also be understood temporally, as a dialectic of two forms of time. As we
have seen, the dialectic of concrete and abstract labor results in an intrinsic
dynamic characterized by a peculiar treadmill pattern. Because each new level
of productivity is redetermined as a new base level, this dynamic tends to
become ongoing and is marked by ever-increasing levels of productivity. Considered
temporally, this intrinsic dynamic of capital, with its treadmill pattern,
entails an ongoing directional movement of time, a "flow of history."
In other words, the mode of concrete time we are examining can be considered historical
time, as constituted in capitalist society. (p. 293)
the dialectical process at the heart of capitalism's immanent
dynamic entails the constitution, spread, and ongoing transformation of
historical determinate forms of subjectivity, interactions, and social values.
(This is implied by Marx's understanding of his categories as determinations of
forms of social existence, grasping both social objectivity and subjectivity in
their intrinsic relatedness.) (p. 294)
As surplus value, measured in quantity, is
both the end and the means of capitalist society, the tighter administrative control
to formalize and rationalize our life may be induced by capitalism.
The socially general mode of scientific, technical, and
organizational knowledge and practice that emerge in the course of capitalist
development are constituted historically in a social context that is determined
by an abstract, homogeneous, quantitative social dimension and, hence, is
geared toward ongoing increases in productivity and efficiency. Not only are the various aspects
of labor's use value dimension developed and utilized in order to serve the
ends given by the value-determined framework, but they also
function structurally to reinforce and reconstitute this framework --
that is, they function as attributes of capital. ...
What I have called the "appropriation" of the use value dimension by that of value thus can be seen as a process in which the use value dimension is structured by means of the sort of formal rationality whose source is the value dimension. The result is the tendency in modern life which Weber described in terms of the growing (formal) rationalization of all spheres of life, and which Horkheimer sought to articulate in terms of the growing instrumentalization of the world. Because this process increasingly involves the substantive dimension of labor and social life -- that is, the administrative rationalization of both production and the institutions of social and political life in postliberal capitalism -- Horkheimer located its source in labor per se. However, the ultimate ground of this substantive development is not the concrete dimension of labor but, rather, its value dimension. (p. 354)
What I have called the "appropriation" of the use value dimension by that of value thus can be seen as a process in which the use value dimension is structured by means of the sort of formal rationality whose source is the value dimension. The result is the tendency in modern life which Weber described in terms of the growing (formal) rationalization of all spheres of life, and which Horkheimer sought to articulate in terms of the growing instrumentalization of the world. Because this process increasingly involves the substantive dimension of labor and social life -- that is, the administrative rationalization of both production and the institutions of social and political life in postliberal capitalism -- Horkheimer located its source in labor per se. However, the ultimate ground of this substantive development is not the concrete dimension of labor but, rather, its value dimension. (p. 354)
We are forced to labor harder and controlled more, but we are not alone that are dominated and affected by capitalistic drive. The earth is, too.
As self-valoring value, capital consumes material nature to produce
material wealth -- not as an end, however, but as a means of expanding
surplus-value, of extracting and absorbing as much surplus labor time from the
working population as possible. This transformation of matter into
units of objectified time is a one-way, rather than a cyclical. process of
productive consumption. In this respect, capital-determined production is
like slash-and-burn agriculture on a "higher" level; it consumes the
source of material wealth and then moves on. Capitalist production, in Marx's
words, "only develops the technique and the degree of combination of the
social process of production by simultaneously undermining the basic source of
all wealth -- the earth and the worker." (pp. 382-383)
We should control capitalism, not be controlled by it. We certainly can control it, for it is we that constitute capitalism. Postone concludes Chapter 9 as follows.
In terms of what I have developed in this work, Marx's conception of
the overcoming of capitalism can be understood in terms of people gaining
control over such quasi-objective developments, over processes of ongoing
and accelerating social transformation, which they themselves have
constituted. Within such a framework, then, the issue is not so much whether
people should try to shape their world -- they already are doing so. Rather,
the issue is the way in which they shape their world and, hence, the nature of
this world and its trajectory. (p. 384)